Consequentialism seems, at the outset, to be a favourable ethical theory, as it provides a straightforward and rational framework for maximising a target value on the basis of determining which act brings about the best possible consequences. For many, one of the most attractive features of the theory is that it maintains an impartiality in cases of individual difference, such as gender, species, race, class or creed. It is, however, considered by some to be too demanding, both in terms of the process of determining the right action and also what it asks the individual to sacrifice for the sake of the larger world. I will focus on the objection from Williams on the latter demand, specifically the impact of Consequentialism’s stipulation of …show more content…
Williams levels his criticism at Utilitarianism, the most widely recognised Consequentialist theory, which aims to bring about the greatest happiness and minimise suffering. I will consider Brink’s defence of Utilitarianism but find that ultimately he fails to answer Williams claim that the Utilitarian requirement of complete impartiality prescribes an implausible moral task, by failing to allow for agent-centric concerns or give preference to an agent’s personal desires over those of others.
Williams (1973: 99) makes his objection to Consequentialism by investigating through two examples how the Utilitarian outlook fails to account for considerations of personal integrity when calculating normative directives. While Williams does not offer a firm definition of the term, we can take it that by integrity he means, that faculty of an individual to initiate actions that further his own interests and by doing so maintain a harmonious concept of self (Blackburn 2008: 187). Williams (1973: 112-113) refers to these interests of an agent as projects or commitments. His concern is that Utilitarianism
…show more content…
Put simply, Jim is faced with the option of killing one Indian to save nineteen (Williams 1973: 98-99). Utilitarianism obviously states that he should do so on the basis that he would increase utility by saving nineteen lives (Williams 1973: 99). The problem with this for Williams is not the outcome of the Utilitarian prescription but the lack of consideration it gives to Jim’s personal point of view (1973: 99). We can imagine that Jim’s very identity might include principles of nonviolence which he has committed to, or perhaps he is in South America to do relief work with Indigenous communities and so the act of killing one of the people he came to help is abhorrent to him. Though Williams (1973: 117) admits that, even when Jim’s commitments are accounted for, the right act still seems to be that Jim should kill the one to save the many, the point he is making against Utilitarianism is not that it fails in a particular case to come up with the correct normative directive, but that it fails to give appropriate weighting to an agent’s
Utilitarianism is a practical doctrine that is widely accepted in modern society’s economics, politic, and ethics. Utilitarian is driven by the pursuit of happiness. For a utilitarian, everything that will be helpful in the pursuit is considered good. In utilitarianism, an action is good or evil based on its consequences on the happiness of an individual and the happiness of the community. Similar to other doctrine, utilitarianism is not without a flaw. Bernard Williams, in his paper Utilitarianism and Integrity, voices his primary concern in regard to utilitarianism by providing two concrete examples to demonstrate how utilitarianism is only concerned about the consequences of the action and not about the means used to get there. Williams argues that utilitarianism fails to acknowledge the integrity of a person because the ultimate goal of utilitarianism is to produce the greatest happiness overall.
Morality, thus, should not be contingent upon conditions or expectations of reciprocity nor should it exclude personal feelings such as love, as it is particularly this characteristic that prevents one from alienation. Railton believes that subjective consequentialism, which requires one to perform before-action deliberate to yield the best consequence, is what produces alienation causing not only “psychological affliction” on oneself, but also to others (137). So, when moral actions become the means for yet another end, one is not acting for the good as an end in itself. Acknowledging the misconception–utilitarian understanding–of consequentialism, Railton expounds upon “sophisticated consequentialism,” which is objective consequentialism in form, but does not endorse subjective consequentialism, leaving space for other forms of decision-making such as love (153). In essence, sophisticated consequentialism is developing dispositions that, ultimately, lead to good, so that one can “allocate” time efficiently, and at the same time able to justify or judge one’s action based on universal morality
Opponents of Act Utilitarianism attempt to argue that Act Utilitarianism (henceforth AU) does not account for justice when applied to ethical dilemmas. It is the authors opinion that these claims are factually incorrect and this essay shall attempt to prove this through analysis of common arguments against AU, and modifying AU to allow for justice to be more readily accounted for.
Williams has a recurring gripe with the ideas of utilitarianism. He believes that in making a utilitarian decision one must forget his integrity, for in making his decision, it is not his personal reputation which takes priority.
Utilitarianism is a moral theory according to which an action is right if and only if it conforms to the principle of utility. An action conforms to the principle of utility if and only if its performance will be more productive of pleasure or happiness, or more preventive of pain and happiness, than any alternative. The rightness of an action entirely depends on the value of its consequences, this is why the theory is described as consequentialist. The “separateness of persons” is an objection against utilitarianism stating that the theory fails to recognize people as distinct individuals. It rejects the allowance of one person’s loss to be offset by another person’s gain, and it is only the net sum total that ultimately matters. Recognition of the “separateness of persons” is needed to put constraints on such trade offs. In this essay I will lay out the theory of utilitarianism and explain the “separateness of persons” objection presented by John Rawls and Robert Nozick. Ultimately I do think they present a successful argument, since utilitarianism is detached from individuals it can lead to grotesquely immoral consequences when put into practice.
Sheehy, Paul. "Doing the Right Thing (Part II): Challenges to Utilitarianism." The Richmond Journal of Philosophy. Richmond Journal, Mar. 2008.
It can be considered then, that yes, utilitarianism is demanding. This assignment will endeavour to define the statement “Is Utilitarianism too demanding?” it will also discuss the arguments presented by Geoffrey Scarre.
This week’s discussion seems to be very interesting and can be looked at many different ways, as we explore the ethical framework we start with consequentialist ethics. This deals with three (3) things, ethical egoism, contractualism, and utilitarianism. This type of ethics asks the following questions: What will happen if I do a certain act? Who will be affected and how would this affect them? How would other alternatives or decisions affect or producer different outcomes (Arrigo & Williams, 2008, p. 145)?
In the book, “The Element of Moral Philosophy”, James Rachels explores the several criticisms of Utilitarianism. In this essay, I will touch on these criticisms, outlining the major implications they propose to Utilitarianism. I will also explain why many of the notions proposed against Utilitarianism are self-serving, and instead serve to improve the general good of a minority population, which contradicts the Utilitarian theory of equating moral aptitude to the general good of a majority population, and that in this respect a greater consequence is achieved. Lastly, I will demonstrate how many societal values have a Utilitarian basis, which proves that Utilitarianism can be salvaged in the face of most criticisms.
Classical utilitarianism is a normative ethical theory which holds that an action can only be considered as morally right where its consequences bring about the greatest amount of good to the greatest number (where 'good' is equal to pleasure minus pain). Likewise, an action is morally wrong where it fails to maximise good. Since it was first articulated in the late 19th Century by the likes of Jeremy Bentham and later John Stewart Mill, the classical approach to utilitarianism has since become the basis for many other consequentialist theories such as rule-utilitarianism and act-utilitarianism upon which this essay will focus (Driver, 2009). Though birthed from the same
In this essay, I will argue that utilitarianism cannot be defended against the injustice objection. Utilitarians may be able to reply to the injustice objection in some cases by invoking one of two replies, the ‘Long term consequences’ reply, in which utilitarians will avoid unjust actions that increase short-term utility because in the long-term they will not lead to the greatest good. The other reply that may help utilitarianism avoid injustice in some cases is the ‘Secondary principles’ reply, where some rule-based principles such as not murdering (because it generally decreases happiness) may avoid injustice. However, I will focus on the ‘bite the bullet’ objection,
“...the happiness which forms the utilitarian standard of what is right in conduct is not the agent’s own happiness but that of all concerned. As between his own happiness and that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator.”(MILLS, Utilitarism)
Consequentialism is a category of normative ethics theory which holds that morally rightness or wrongness of an action is sorely determined by the consequences of the movement. That is, it focuses decision making upon the potential outcomes of an action, and this outcome becomes the only standard of morality - the ends justify the means.
James Rachels argues against utilitarianism on the bases of justice, rights, and backward looking reasons. In this paper I will address Rachels reasoning for rights to be a means of denying a consequentialist view, counter-examples to support his reasons, and why utilitarianism ultimately should be rejected. Utilitarianism is an ethical theory in which only the maximum amount of happiness for the most amount of people matters. It is a consequence based philosophy where an action is morally right if it benefits the majority of society, which creates many loop holes for injustice. Utilitarianism opens a door to exploit others in a morally inept fashion, allowing people to believe their actions are right when actually they are morally wrong.
Its general outline is the moral rightness of an action is determined by outcomes. For example, a student was struggling to help an old lady who has fallen on ground while other people do not even care about it and a student had to leave in a hurry. However, he helped her and a lady offered cordial thanks. As the example is illustrated, the act is good if its consequences are good, but if its consequences are bad then the act is wrong. Shaw et al(2013, p. 63) emphasizes that consequentialists determine what is right by weighing the ratio of good to bad that an action will produce. According to consequentialists, the decision of the Dean of Harvard Business School is simply explained as the result of decision which rejected all applicants who attempted to access the information derive a conclusion which Dean Clark observed their belief, principles and it shows making own decisions is always with responsibility for actions. In addition, utilitarianism will be applied on this case because this theory is in contrast with egoism which can be defined by Shaw et al(2013, p. 63) as egoism contends that an act is morally right if and only if it best promotes an agent’s long term interest.’. It means self-interesting is most important key point whether going into action or not. However, Utilitarianism is focused on more about ‘achieving the