The argument presented by William James in “The Will to Believe” covers theistic beliefs and also includes various philosophical issues as well as matters of practical life. James's primary concern is to argue that Clifford's Rule is irrational. According to Clifford's Rule, one should avoid error at all costs and ultimately risk the loss of certain truths. James claims that Clifford's Rule is just one intellectual strategy and then makes an argument to seek truth by any means available, even at the risk of error or being completely false. James is not arguing against conforming one's belief to the evidence. Nor is he arguing against the importance of evidence. His argument is against withholding beliefs whenever there is little evidence, …show more content…
Given that our will plays a role in determining our belief, James argues if we should embrace this as a fact of psychological life, or struggle against it.
William James maintains that pure reason is never the final factor of what we believe. He states that our emotions and desires partially determine what beliefs we have. We can, through will, have belief in any live hypothesis. A dead hypothesis means we have previously exercised our will in a certain way, like by being influenced by the opinions of those around us and chose to belief the hypothesis is inapplicable. James notes that we have the duty to believe the truth and the duty to not believe the false. In order to believe the truth, we must have beliefs and so we risk having false beliefs. According to James, we make a decision between two hypotheses, also called an
…show more content…
I think that it is too difficult to base live, dead, forced and trivial options when we must take into account the society as well as the believes of those around us. It is obvious that any rule that restricts belief in any way might shut us off from certain truths. However, there are many examples where one risks everything and loses. For example, choosing to go on the Titanic where the ship was sunk. Although it's debatable whether it's better to have risked and died than to have not risked at all. I think that it is still "better to have loved and lost than to have not loved at all." but it's debatable whether it's better to have risked and died than to have not risked at all. The problems I run into are whether dead options can be made live? “Be a Buddhist” and “Be a Christian,” may both be live, to someone who have views that reflect both religions. Another example could be the idea that germs cause disease. This was probably not a live hypothesis for people back in the medieval era, because they did not know what actually caused sickness. People lacked evidence to support a live hypothesis. But today’s day in age, we have technology and medical advancements that we rely on to kill those diseases. A once “dead option” would now live. I think that this argument results in too much indecisiveness. I commend James’ efforts to believe in ideas, regardless of the amount
William James (1897), on the other hand, attempts to define the permissible cases in which it is intellectually respectable to believe without sufficient evidence. James (1897) begins by providing three criterion for judging beliefs: either beliefs are 1) living or dead; 2) forced or avoidable; or 3) momentous or trivial.
In the pages of the bible one can find an early answer to an ancient debate. Jesus appears before Thomas whom had doubted Jesus’s existence and says, “Because you have seen me, have you believed? Blessed are they who do not see, and yet believed.”(John 20:29). Jesus reveres those who were able to accept his existence without proof, while scorning Thomas for his doubt. The struggle between belief and doubt is seen throughout the course of history. The novel A Prayer For Owen Meany by John Irving also attempts to address the battle between these seemingly mutually exclusive principles. The novel centers around a boy named Owen Meany, who believes his future is predetermined for him by God. The protagonist is a man named John Wheelwright, who
Throughout the Gospel of John the term “belief” is used in multiple ways for different reasons. Belief is employed as a means to give the reader motivation to believe in Jesus and God which will bring them to eternal glory and happiness. This belief can be rewarded with eternal life, as well as a personal connection to Jesus Christ. God can also be seen and believed in if one only believes in Jesus and allows for a wholesome connection to the Father and Son. In addition to beginning to understand the use of “belief” in the Gospel of John, one must correctly infer from his words and deduce their meaning.
If you have no good reason to think that your belief is true, then you cannot rationally maintain it. 4. REVISION. We cannot rationally maintain our evaluative beliefs. [2, 3]
Without evidence, nothing can accurately be proven true. In his article, You Know I Learned Something Today: Stan Marsh and the Ethics of Belief, Henry Jacoby quotes English mathematician and philosopher W.K Clifford when he says it is “wrong always, everywhere, and for anyone to believe anything upon insufficient evidence” (Jacoby 58). The Christian religion is strongly based on Faith; the faith that the Bible is nonfiction, that there is a heaven and a hell, and most importantly that there is in fact a God. Due to the fact that none of these subjects have any documented evidence supporting their claims, is it really in society’s best interest to believe in them? If humans create beliefs based on the simple fact that they cannot be disproven; however, they have no solid evidence they can be proven then it is all turned into a
It is clear that many philosophers fail to agree on many arguments and debates. As for The Ethics of Belief, it refers to many questions of it being right or wrong to believe anything and everything regarding sufficient evidence, from ethics, epistemology, and psychology. “Clifford's principle” is better yet known as the principle which Clifford states it is wrong to believe on the basis of insufficient evidence. In Clifford's “Ethics of Belief”, he attempts to defend his principle. After reading through Van Inwagen’s “Is it Wrong, Everywhere, Always, and for Anyone to Believe Anything Upon Insufficient Evidence”, it is no secret that he begs to differ with Clifford’s beliefs.
If one never asks, or questions, or even tests one's own belief, whether that be the belief in the physical or in the beliefs that aren't physical, then they are guilty not by law, but by conscience. Clifford also states: Into this, for good or ill, is woven every belief of every man who has speech of his fellows. An awful privilege, and an awful responsibility, that we should help to create the world in which posterity will live. Which shows it is not only wrong to believe anything upon insufficient evidence but also to believe something just because one told another to believe something. Beliefs are passed down from generation to generation, and without the question of those beliefs, those beliefs cannot become one's true beliefs because of the insufficient platform in which one had begun to believe on. Clifford states that this is morally wrong. Arguments based on luck cannot be valid because arguments based on luck are not based on evidence or reasonable
This section provides us with two selections from the essays of William K. Clifford (1845-1879) and William James (1842-1910). Clifford's essay, The Ethics of Belief, is based on the concept of evidentialism. This concept 'holds that we should not accept any statement as true unless we have good evidence to support its truth'; (Voices of Wisdom, 346). James wrote his essay, The Will to Believe, as a response to Clifford's essay where he endorsed a philosophy called pragmatism.
As we know many people have a stance on religion just like WK Clifford who has a very strong view about religion, but some do not agree. William James for examples thinks that, Clifford’s principles should be not to be applied to religious beliefs because as he points out moral questions cannot simply be settled by the facts. James argues that we have a right to believe in some cases, when supporting evidence may be lacking. James sees the basic idea of religion as having two parts that the best things are the eternal things, and that you will be better off in the here and now if you believe this. An example of something we almost all believe in without sufficient evidence, is the emotions we feel often every day. The many emotions we feel everyday such as happiness, anger, or even sympathy are very often morally relevant to us. Emotions are not settled by facts we just feel them and for sometimes no reason at all. Like
William James was an American existentialist philosopher. His essay, “The Will to Believe” focused on why someone should believe in something that may not have definitive evidence. William James asserts in his essay that, “If your heart does not want a world of moral reality, your head will assuredly never make you believe in one.” I argue that this quote is used to defend believing in something that can’t be proven or disproven through science, i.e. God, and means that some options are self-fulfilling and need to be believed to make them real.
In this essay, I will criticize W.K. Clifford’s main claim that it is always wrong, everywhere, and for anyone, to believe anything upon insufficient evidence. I will prove it is not wrong to form a belief without sufficient evidence, by engaging with ineffability. In the first section, I will begin by presenting Clifford’s main argument for why it is always wrong to believe anything upon insufficient evidence. In the second section, I will define and explain The Representation Principle. Since Clifford does not clearly define what constitutes “sufficient evidence,” I will employ The Representation Principle as one requirement for sufficient evidence. The Representation Principle states: it is impossible to acquire sufficient evidence if someone is unable to fully represent all of the relevant information. In the third section, I will present my argument for refraining from forming beliefs, also referenced as The “RFB” Argument. I conclude that in some cases it is wrong for human beings
We can see that William James proposes two different approaches to thinking for our own choice. In this quote, he teaches that skepticism is a healthy manner of thinking and that skepticism isn’t an avoidance of belief, but rather a method to achieve facts by inquiring. Is it better to accept what’s proven wrong or adamantly ignore other truths of matters in life? Regarding this question, for example, the outcome of my analysis of literature is constantly being question in order for me to think deeper, typically because I generally take the fact as face value. Is that metaphor the only thing representing the era of the character? How exactly does that metaphor represent the era in relation to the theme? Prove it.
Our belief states are determined by the external factors, for example, perceived complexity and priming ethics is an interesting subject and everyone lives by their thoughts and their ways. Everyone lives by a different code. The difference between morality and ethics is that morality is about primary making the right choices and ethics is proper reasoning. In the essay “The ethics of belief” by W. K. Clifford, he argues that if anything on insufficient evidence, then it’s unethical. In this essay *I will defend the hypothesis that if anything doesn’t have enough evidence then it is unethical. * I agree with some of his (don’t agree) (agree in some parts)
It is in W. K. Clifford’s essay The Ethics of Belief in which the author argues that a belief system based on anything but evidence is immoral. This argument is made in response to Blaise Pascal’s suggestion that it is practically reasonable to live as though God exists as there is no loss in the wager itself should God exist or not. The case of a ship owner is offered as an example to illustrate the point for genuine justification. Despite fears that his vessel may not be seaworthy, a ship owner puts those doubts aside and allows the ship, full of emigrants in search of a better life, to set sail. Having safely sailed numerous voyages and weathered many storms in the past, the ship owner felt confident in putting his trust in Providence.
This concept differs from James’ characterization of belief. James is a Relativist; therefore, he believes that we will never really know the “truth”. James believes that each individual should think for themselves and do whatever they personally think is right. He believes that religion is something that is a live, forced, and momentous option. Religion is something that will require a leap of faith, but the knowledge process allows for this. James suggests that one should take a leap of faith and then wait and see what happens next and then reevaluate. In the end if everyone does this our quality of life will generally improve and as a group everyone will tend to move toward the