• Pro-life and Pro-choice points out our attention toward the fetus, the other emphasizes the pregnant woman. o Pro-life supporters emphasize the issue of the rights of the unborn. o Pro-choice supporters stress the importance of the rights of the pregnant woman.
• The criteria of personhood is necessary to specify what we mean by a person.
• Initially, much of the debate about abortion centered around the question of the moral status of the fetus – In particular, if and when the fetus is a person. o It began sufficient conditions, which are conditions that if present would guarantee personhood. The structure of the argument looks like this: Criterion to personhood to right to life. The transition between these three pieces are where justification is needed. o A number of criteria have been advanced for personhood. Some of these result in conferring personhood quite early in fetal development, sometimes from the moment of conception. Some examples of the criterions are listed below.
▪ Conceived by humans criterion is any one conceived by human parents is considered a human being.
▪ The genetic structure argument maintains that a human genetic code is a sufficient condition for personhood. All the genetic information for the fully formed human being is present in the fetus at the time of conception; therefore, it has the rights of a person.
▪ Physical resemblance criterion claims that something that looks human is human.
▪ Presence of a soul criterion is often evoked by
human from usually two months after conception to birth. It defines an embryo as a human or
While parts of both may be true, both cannot stand side by side as completely true when discussing abortion. As they stand today, fetus rights and female rights are incompatible in arena of abortion. Even the “other side” agrees that the two cannot stand shoulder to shoulder. In a chapter entitled “Abortion Does Not Violate Human Rights”, Christian Beenfeldt quotes Brian McKinely when claiming that female rights have a higher precedence than fetus rights: “It’s actually quite simple. You cannot have two entities with equal rights occupying one body. One will automatically have veto power over the other.” So one question remains, which more important, fetus rights or female rights? The winner of this question can be decided by one simple factor: is the fetus to be considered a true, living human being at the point of conception, or does true human life not begin until after birth? A clarification should be made here, however. In this paper it will be assumed that everyone involved in this debate considers a newborn child to be a human being. That is, at the moment of birth, a child either becomes a human being or continues to be a human being; regardless of the fetus’s life state before birth, it will be assumed that all agree that birth “confirms”, so to speak, the life and human existence of the newborn.
The debate about the legality of abortion involves debating the legal status of the fetus. If the fetus is a person, anti-choice activists argue, then abortion is murder and should be illegal. Even if the fetus is a person, though, abortion may have justified as necessary to women’s body self-govern but that wouldn’t mean that abortion is automatically ethical. Perhaps the state can’t force women to carry pregnancies to term, but it could argue that it is the most ethical choice.
After coming to the United States, the first controversial issue that caught my attention was personhood and abortion. Most of the people that I had conversations with were concerned about this issue and were against the personhood legislation in Oklahoma which prohibits abortion and birth control. Mostly the women viewed the whole issue as an infringement upon their rights. Likewise, the men were concerned about the rights of their loved ones. Though they are the choice of a woman and are private, the issue is still morally challenging for everyone as it involves emotion, culture and spiritual beliefs. Therefore, it is an issue that appeals to people’s emotion apart from their political and religious stands, as it involves lives and motherhood. It affects people emotionally and physically, too. Most importantly, no woman wants to be called a murderer simply because she chooses to terminate a pregnancy. Most supporters of personhood legislation assert that personhood begins at fertilization, while most pro-choice people claim that personhood does not begin at fertilization and it is the choice of a woman to decide whether or not she wants to continue her pregnancy or use methods of birth control. However, I believe that once a fetus has become receptive to senses and pain, it should not be aborted. Therefore, the entire debate about personhood is when the life of a person begins or at what stage in the human life
When fetus become a live and considered as a human being? Based on the California and USA constitution fetus are only considered as human being after eight week of period of time after conception. However, other 17 state in The USA claim that the fetus are human being the mo-ment the baby is conception. There are a lot of different rules and rules through the globe when a fetus is a human being. There is no such a universal rule that everyone agree with, but the Ameri-can convention on human right is the most known international treaty. The treaty is signed by the 24 countries stating the human beings have the right beginning at the moment of conception. American Convention on Human Rights of 1969, signed by 24 Latin American countries, alt-hough the USA is not the party of the treaty. However, what makes
One may argue that the definition of moral status pertains to a viable being or entity. At what point is a developing fetus considered a viable being? According to Lee & George (2008), regardless of their age or size, a human being has basic rights. The notion of moral status is to have value and also refers to entities that have rights (Grand Canyon University [GCU], 2015).
Out of all modern social controversies, perhaps the most heated controversy is that of abortion. In today’s society you are either a Pro-life or a Pro-choice, there is not a middle ground. Pro-life are individuals who believe abortion is immoral and should be stop for the wellbeing of women and unborn babies. In contrast, the Pro-choice individuals do not necessarily promote abortion, they just believe women should be the ones to make decisions over their bodies and health. Although the two main sides of the abortion debate have concerns for human life, pro-life activists worries more about the fetus and morals, a clear difference from the pro-choice that worries more for the women and their rights. Based on the points I explored, the pro-choice arguments are stronger than pro-life arguments. Most of both groups arguments comes from peer-reviewed researches from well-known sources to support each individual concept. Effects on women,socio-politics, and fetus are some of the main point of conflicts between the pro-life and pro-choice advocates.
When an embryo should be considered an actual human has a variety of answers, “some have sought to reject that the early human embryo is a human being, according to one view, the cells that comprise the early embryo are a bundle of homogeneous cells that exist in the same membrane but do not form a human organism because the cells do not function in a coordinated way to regulate and preserve a single life”.(Siegel)
opposite claim; that the unborn child, because it is a developing human being, possesses a moral status
Following that, one must determine whether the fetus’ environment really determines whether or not it is a human. One may say, the fetus is clearly not human until it is born. To that, I would ask, does location really change a human’s personhood? Afterall, humans live in all different locations. A fetus is not human merely because it is inside of the mother.
In both cases, resorting to other grounds solves, or rather, dissolves, the contradiction by eliminating the need to make the determinations which create the contradiction — specifically whether or not the fetus is a person and whether or not the woman has the right to control her own body. These determinations are simply unnecessary; one
Physicians, biologists, and other scientists agree that conception marks the beginning of the life of a human being—a being that is alive and is a member of the human species. There is overwhelming agreement on this point in countless medical, biological, and scientific writings.
Inbuilt in the nature of the personhood theory, therefore, is to restrict any other human interest or value in grounding human rights. This raises the question, why is personhood any more determinant than any other concept or human interest. This question becomes all the more pertinent when the personhood account is applied to human rights recognised in contemporary human rights culture.
“it is said that to draw a line, to choose a point in this development and say ‘before this point the thing is not a person, after this point it is a person’ is to make an arbitrary choice… It is concluded that the fetus is a person from the moment of conception. But this conclusion does not follow. Similar things might be said about the development of an acorn into an oak tree, and it does not follow that acorns are oak trees” (Thompson 1971).
In order to be considered a legal person, there are physical and conceptual requirements. The physical requirement to be a legal person is to be ‘born alive’. In R v Poulton (1832) 5 C & P 329 at 330, it is said that the fetus becomes a legal person when ‘the whole body is brought into the world.’ Conceptually, a legal person must be ‘…an enclosed, bounded and sovereign being…’ and a ‘…rational person…’ who can ‘…exercise autonomy over his own person…’ In other words; they must be capable of self-government. It is difficult to define legal personhood narrowly due to its interpretation being dependent on context and purpose but this is generally a universally accepted definition.